Discussion about this post

User's avatar
Melvin Clive Bird (Behnke)'s avatar

Okay, this overview of Heidegger’s philosophical development part 3 offers a reductive narrative of his thought. The division into early, middle, and late periods—centered on Sein und Zeit, Beiträge zur Philosophie, and the late writings on language and the Geviert—follows a familiar structure in Heidegger scholarship. It rightly identifies the so-called middle period as crucial for understanding Heidegger’s confrontation with the history of philosophy, especially through texts like Beiträge, Einführung in die Metaphysik, and Geschichte des Seyns. The passage’s focus on Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the notion of the “first Beginning” accurately reflects Heidegger’s narrative of the originary disclosure of Being.

Where the presentation falters is in the treatment of Heidegger’s key concepts and the philosophical nuances of his project. The account refers to Ereignis in passing but fails to convey its centrality as the middle period’s guiding notion. Heidegger’s thinking in the 1930s and 40s is not merely a critique of metaphysical decline but a rethinking of the very “event” of Being’s historical disclosure. Without this, the narrative risks flattening into a tale of mere loss and error, as if Heidegger simply diagnosed a fatalistic fall from an originary truth. In fact, Heidegger insists on a more complex “destining” (Geschick)—a historical sending that both conceals and grants Being, always with the potential for a new beginning.

The explanation of concepts like Gestell and techne feels imprecise. Gestell, Heidegger’s term for the enframing of Being in the technological age, is not just an outgrowth of logos’ nihilating power but a historically specific mode of revealing. Reducing it to a linear consequence of logos risks missing Heidegger’s historical thinking, which is not causal but responsive to the way Being shows itself in each epoch.

There are also terminological missteps. The awkward use of “existent” and transliterations like sushcheye muddle rather than clarify the delicate distinction between Sein (Being), Seiendes (beings), and Dasein (the being for whom Being is a question). Moreover, metaphors like the “ray with trajectory and vector” betray Heidegger’s own care to avoid mechanistic or geometrical figures in favor of more topological images: the clearing (Lichtung), the path (Holzweg), or the region (Gegnet).

The analysis of Plato and Aristotle is competent in outlining their roles in consolidating metaphysics, but it simplifies Heidegger’s more nuanced engagements with their thought. Heidegger does not merely see them as the “end of the first Beginning” in a pejorative sense; rather, he explores how their thinking both conceals and preserves possibilities for rethinking Being. Especially in Aristotle, Heidegger finds a profound meditation on energeia that modernity would flatten into objectified presence.

Most crucially, the text implies that Heidegger’s philosophy converges teleologically on the theory of Dasein as the culmination of the historical-philosophical process. This overlooks Heidegger’s “turn” (Kehre), in which Dasein becomes less central as he moves towards a more historical-topological thinking of Being itself. The “history of Being” is not a straight line from origin to fall, but a complex movement of revealing and concealing, with possibilities for new beginnings.

In short, while the passage offers a competent and structured overview, it lacks philosophical precision and depth. It reads as an external summary rather than an immanent unfolding of Heidegger’s thinking. To do justice to Heidegger, such an account would need to let the terms and gestures of his thought arise from within their own questioning—not imposed as external labels or historical vectors. The story of metaphysics is not simply a fall from grace but an eventful history that still holds open the possibility of another beginning.

Expand full comment
Summa Neutra's avatar

Personally, I don't adhere to the notion of continuity when it comes to understanding the trajectory of Heidegger’s thought. Nevertheless, we can observe certain recurrences: resorts, entanglements, circumvolutions. Dasein and its analytic culminate in Sein und Zeit, yet it remains something spectral, like a possibility, a myth, a kind of non-substantial Adam Kadmon, without attributes, predication, causality, reflection, telos, or spatiality/temporality. All the frameworks that enable the understanding of man as Dasein are themselves products of the deep structure of metaphysics. We say that man is Dasein, but clearly, Dasein is not the man. It is impossible to construct a straightforward anthropology of Dasein; the internal analytic of its own being-in-the-world does not permit it. And yet, we constantly see how tautology traps man within the continuity of Gerede and everydayness. From the analytic of Dasein, the entire continuity of the colossal metaphysical edifice begins to tremble; and eventually collapses. This collapse, as Heidegger sees it, is not simply a destruction, but an exposure: an unveiling of the inner scaffolding of metaphysics, brought into the light most fully through Nietzsche. Paradoxically, Nietzsche becomes both the apex and the termination of metaphysical thought; the one who, in fulfilling its logic, reveals its limits. For Heidegger, Nietzsche is not merely a critic of metaphysics; he is its final consummation. In the figure of Nietzsche, metaphysics becomes transparent to itself. The will to power, the revaluation of all values, and the eternal return; these are not just ideas, but the last great metaphysical gestures. They expose the hidden essence of Western thought: the will to mastery, the reduction of Being to presence, the relentless pursuit of certainty and ground. Yet Nietzsche also opens a path. Without Nietzsche, Heidegger could not leap beyond metaphysics toward the question of Being itself. Nietzsche is a passage, a necessary traversal, through which Heidegger reaches back; not to the classical or scholastic tradition, but to the origin: the Pre-Socratics. There, in the early Greek thinkers, Being had not yet been obscured by the conceptual machinery of metaphysics. It was experienced, hinted at, spoken poetically, not yet imprisoned in the logic of representation and correspondence. Socrates marks a turning. With him, and more precisely, with Plato, the identification of Being with truth begins, and truth itself becomes correctness, agreement, proposition. The event of Being is reduced to a metaphysical object, subordinated to the idea, to presence, to logos. From there, a long history unfolds: from Plato to Descartes, from Descartes to Nietzsche. The history of metaphysics is the history of the forgetting of Being.

The analytic of Dasein in Being and Time is thus not a final philosophy, but a beginning. It is a way of disclosing our thrown, temporal, finite existence as the site where Being reveals itself and where it has also been forgotten. The collapse of metaphysics is not merely an end, but a clearing. It is in this clearing (Lichtung) that Heidegger hopes to listen once more to the silent call of Being.

Nietzsche stands at the edge of this clearing, shouting the death of God, laughing in the abyss of nihilism. But in that very laughter, in that very collapse, Heidegger hears something more: not the end of philosophy, but the possibility of another beginning.

Expand full comment
3 more comments...

No posts